请输入您要查询的字词:

 

单词 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1646–1716)
释义
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1646–1716)

Mathematics
  • on a wide range of subjects, who was, with Newton, the founder of the calculus. Newton’s discovery of differential calculus was perhaps ten years earlier than Leibniz’s, but Leibniz was the first to publish his account, written independently of Newton, in 1684. Soon after, he published an exposition of integral calculus that included the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus. He also wrote on other branches of mathematics, making significant contributions to the development of symbolic logic.


Statistics
  • Leibniz graduated from U Leipzig at the age of seventeen. In 1667 he was awarded a doctorate in law by U Altdorf. In 1673 he was elected FRS. In 1675, in Paris, he developed the dx notation for differentials. In 1679 he developed the binary system. Leibniz was an assiduous letter writer with more than 600 correspondents including all the leading mathematicians of the day. He studied all areas of mathematics and is credited with devising the diagrams popularized by Venn. His later years were much taken up with disputes on priority concerning the work on differentiation and integration: he was accused of plagiarism by a supporter of Sir Isaac Newton (who had derived equivalent results independently of Leibniz).

    http://scienceworld.wolfram.com/biography/Leibniz.html Fuller biography and portrait.


Computer
  • One of the supreme polymath intellects of the 17th century, his significance to the future science of computing was his exploration of binary numbers and arithmetic, which interested him from an early age and was fully laid out in his Explication de l’arithmétique binaire (1703). His many other contributions to knowledge include the philosophical theory of monads and the invention of calculus as it is used today (1675, published in 1684; Isaac Newton, who had independently discovered calculus earlier but did not publish until later, falsely contended that Leibniz had stolen ideas from his unpublished notes).


Philosophy
  • Leibniz was born in Leipzig, where he attended university from the age of fifteen, and submitted a thesis for the degree of doctor of law at the age of twenty. In 1667 he entered the service of the Elector of Mainz, where he remained until 1672, engaged largely in political writing. He travelled to Paris in 1672, partly to try to persuade Louis XIV to expel the Turks from Egypt (thereby diverting his attention from Germany; the plan did not succeed). He visited England in 1673, and again in 1676, at which time he had completed his discovery of the differential calculus. In this year he travelled to Amsterdam and met Spinoza, and became librarian to the Duke of Brunswick at Hanover, a post he held until his death. Between 1680 and 1697 he was working on his own system of philosophy. Leibniz was the greatest polymath of modern philosophers, making contributions to mathematics, jurisprudence, and history, as well as philosophy. He corresponded extensively with all the major learned men of the time, and was the founder of the Academy of Berlin.

    Leibniz’s mature philosophical system is both intricate and strange, resting on a small number of highly general principles. The foundation of his thought is the conviction that to each individual there corresponds a complete notion, knowable only to God, from which is deducible all the properties possessed by the individual at each moment in its history. It is contingent that God actualizes the individual that meets such a concept, but his doing so is explicable by the principle of sufficient reason, whereby God had to actualize just that possibility in order for this to be the best of all possible worlds (the thesis subsequently lampooned by Voltaire in Candide). This deducibility of each of an individual’s properties from its complete concept is due to there being an ontological correlate of the complete concept, or in other words a modification of the substance of an individual corresponding to each truth about it. In turn this connects with Leibniz’s belief that relations, including causal relations between separate individuals, are only phenomena bene fundata, or constructions that the mind places upon what are at bottom monadic, non-relational facts. However, Leibniz was entirely hostile to 17th-century atomism, so that eventually the individuals of his mature system are the monads: non-physical individual unities, each ‘windowless’, or independent of other things, and each evolving in a way that is entirely dependent upon their intrinsic natures, but each capable of perceptions that in turn ‘express’ the nature of external reality. It is arguable that at this point Leibniz reverts to an Aristotelian conception of nature as essentially striving to actualize its potential. Naturally it is not easy in such a system to make room for space (which Leibniz considered to be relational), corporeal substance, matter (which again he thought of as a phenomenon bene fundatum), or free will. Along with those of Descartes and Spinoza, that of Leibniz is the third of the great rationalist systems of the 17th century, and in many respects the most unusual. Leibniz’s major works, none of which contains a finally developed account of his system, are Discourse of Metaphysics (1685); The New System (1695); Theodicy (1710); and Monadology (c.1713). His correspondence with Arnauld, Jean Bernoulli, Burcher de Volder, Bartholemew des Bosses, and Clarke has been published in separate volumes, as have his controversy with Bayle, and the Nouveaux Essais which contain his reaction to Locke’s Essay.

    http://www.gwleibniz.com/ A list of internet resources on Leibniz, including his writings

    http://www.phillwebb.net/History/Modern/Leibniz/Leibniz.htm Bibliographies of writings by or on Leibniz


随便看

 

科学参考收录了60776条科技类词条,基本涵盖了常见科技类参考文献及英语词汇的翻译,是科学学习和研究的有利工具。

 

Copyright © 2000-2023 Sciref.net All Rights Reserved
京ICP备2021023879号 更新时间:2024/9/29 21:35:46